Economics of Affirmative Action

views updated

ECONOMICS OF AFFIRMATIVE ACTION

The Supreme Court has mandated that government affirmative action plans must serve some compelling state interest and must be narrowly tailored to further this interest. Economics doesn't have much to say about whether, say, remedying racial discrimination is a compelling interest, but the tools of economics can shed light on what types of affirmative action programs satisfy the narrow tailoring requirement (or least restrictive means test). Economic analysis suggests that the most narrowly tailored affirmative action program (1) will be racially explicit (rather than the Court's current preference for "race neutral means to increase minority participation"); (2) will use a sliding scale of credits in which the size of the racial preferences declines with minority participation; and (3) may at times create "quasi-quotas" that effectively ensure a participation floor for minorities.

The idea that a remedy needs to be tailored to further the government's legitimate interest is captured in part by the unexceptional idea that remedial classifications should not be too overinclusive or underinclusive. The Court, for example, in richmond (city of) V. J. a. croson co. (1989) was particularly concerned about the problem of overinclusion; that is, giving affirmative action preferences to people (such as Aleuts) who were not injured by past discrimination in a particular jurisdiction. However, the same opinion also expressed a strong preference for the "the use of race-neutral means to increase minority business participation." This preference for "race-neutral means"—such as general subsidies for small entrepreneurs—necessarily conflicts with the Court's aversion to overly inclusive programs. If preferring the minuscule number of Aleuts in Richmond is "grossly overinclusive," then extending preferences to a much larger class of whites—as would race-neutral subsidies—a fortiori would fail the narrow tailoring requirement. Narrowly tailoring the beneficiary class for remedial subsidies so that it will not be overinclusive necessitates explicit racial classifications.

Clearly, the Court has something more in mind by narrow tailoring than a mere insistence on not too much over-or underinclusion. Indeed, the Court's decisions suggest that narrow tailoring may also require that racial preferences not unduly burden nonminorities. Government decisionmakers are constitutionally required to remedy discrimination using the least restrictive alternative. Here, too, economic analysis can be of help—especially in evaluating the relative costs (burdens to minorities) and benefits (remedying racial discrimination) of different affirmative action programs. Narrow tailoring implies a sensitivity to the contours and scope of racial preferences and economic analysis is especially attuned to analyzing effects on the margin.

Simple economics suggests that the Court's antipathy for quotas is overstated. Quotas may be more narrowly tailored to achieve the government's remedial interest than many other types of racial preferences. While quotas are imperfectly tailored because they mandate an inflexible level of minority participation, bidding credits (and other preferences) may be poorly tailored because they induce too much uncertainty and volatility in minority participation.

The question of whether affirmative action racial preferences should be implemented with quotas or credits is similar to the more general question of whether laws should take the form of quantity or price regulation. Economists such as Martin Weitzman and Robert Cooter have suggested circumstances where either type of regulation might be the most efficient. Applied to the question of affirmative action, these models suggest that more narrowly tailored programs will exhibit a "sliding scale" of racial preferences in which the size of the preference will vary inversely with the degree of successful minority participation in the program. Under a narrowly tailored program, the farther minority participation falls below what it would be in the absence of discrimination, the larger the racial preference government might legitimately confer.

Sliding-scale preferences may come close to setting aside a minimum quota of contracts for minority bidders, but such quasi-quotas (for fractions of the legitimate remedial goal) are consistent with narrow tailoring when dramatic shortfalls in minority participation would undermine the government's remedial effort. For example, in an industry where the government has a legitimate interest in increasing minority participation to 30 percent (the fair estimate of what it would have been absent discrimination), the government might find that allowing minority participation to fall below 5 percent would affect the long-term viability of all minority business. Under such circumstances, the government might be justified under the narrow tailoring principle in granting substantial bidding credits for 5 percent of government contracts, effectively guaranteeing that at least 5 percent will go to minorities.

Quasi-quotas can be defended as narrowly tailored remedies because they cause decisionmakers to internalize the true social costs of dramatic shortfalls in minority participation. The problem with simple (invariant) bidding credits is that the participation of minorities may fluctuate in ways that are inconsistent with narrow tailoring of the preferences to the government's underlying remedial interest. Quasi-quotas for a fraction of the overall remedial goal dampen this potential damaging fluctuation. And because the quasi-quota would only set aside a fraction of the government's legitimate remedial goal, it would impose a smaller burden on the interests of nonbeneficiaries. Finally, granting minority enterprises guarantees of minimum participation can increase the quality of minority participants—so as to reduce the long-term disparity between minority and nonminority recipients.

Economics also suggests that sometimes government can remedy private discrimination without unduly burdening nonminorities. Government racial preferences in procurement, for example, can counteract private under-utilization in the same market without unduly burdening nonminority firms who are by hypothesis overutilized in the overall market because of their race.

Ian ayres
(2000)

Bibliography

Ayres, Ian 1996 Narrow Tailoring. UCLA Law Review 43: 1781–1838.

Ayres, Ian and Vars, Frederick E. 1998 When Does Private Discrimination Justify Public Affirmative Action? Columbia Law Review 1998:1577–1641.

Cooter, Robert 1984 Prices and Sanctions. Columbia Law Review 84:1523–1560.

About this article

Economics of Affirmative Action

Updated About encyclopedia.com content Print Article