Bhāvaviveka
BHĀVAVIVEKA
BHĀVAVIVEKA (c. 490–570 ce), also known as Bhavya or (in Tibetan) Legs ldan ʾbyed pa; Indian Buddhist philosopher and historian, and founder of the Svātantrika-Mādhyamika school. Born to a royal family in Malyara, in South India (although some Chinese sources claim it was in Magadha, in North India), Bhāvaviveka studied both sūtra and śāstra literatures during his formative years. Having excelled in the art of debate, especially against Hindu apologists of the Sāṃkhya school, he is said to have been the abbot of some fifty monasteries in the region of Dhanyakata, in South India. His chief influences were the writings of Nāgārjuna (second century ce), the founder of the Mādhyamika, and treatises on logic from the traditions of Buddhism (especially Dignāga's works) and Hinduism (especially the Nyāyapraveśa ). His chief philosophical contribution was his attempt at formulating a synthesis of Mādhyamika dialectics and the logical conventions of his time.
As all of Bhāvaviveka's works are lost in the original Sanskrit and preserved only in Tibetan translations, the scholarly world came to know of him only through Candrakīrti (c. 580–650 ce), who refuted Bhāvaviveka's position in the first chapter of the Prasannapadā. It could therefore be argued that current understanding of the Mādhyamika in general has suffered from a one-sided perspective that relies solely on Candrakīrti's rival school, the Prāsaṅgika-Mādhyamika. However, contemporary scholarship no longer neglects Tibetan sources, and thus a more balanced approach has ensued, one that reads Nāgārjuna's seminal writings through the commentaries of both the Prāsaṅgikas and the Svātantrikas.
Nagarjuna, especially as read through the commentaries of Buddhāpalita (c. 470–550 ce), was characterized by many Indian philosophers as a vaitaṇḍika, a nihilist who refused to assume any thesis (pratijñā ) in the course of the ongoing dialogue between Hindu thinkers of various schools and the Buddhists. While Mādhyamika thought had not asserted any claim about ultimate truth/reality (paramārthasatya ), Bhāvaviveka's independent reasoning (svatantra-anumāna ) was applied to conventional truth/reality (samvṛtisatya ) as a means of rescuing logico-linguistic conventions (vyavahāra ) from a systematic negation (prasaṅga ) that opened the school to charges of nihilism. While Bhāvaviveka accepted the Mādhyamika view that ultimately (paramārthataḥ ) no entities could be predicated with any form of existence, he was willing to employ such predication on a conventional level. In order to maintain the reality and utility of traditional Buddhist categories for talking about the path of spiritual growth while denying the ultimate reality of such categories, he employed a syllogistic thesis (pratijñā ), a philosophic strategy that was nearly incomprehensible to scholars of the Mādhyamika, who knew this school only through Candrakīrti's Prāsaṅgika systematization.
In order to affirm a thesis on the conventional level while denying it ultimately, Bhāvaviveka creatively reinterpreted the key Mādhyamika doctrine of the two truths (satyadvaya ). In his Madhyamārthasaṃgraha, he propounds two levels of ultimacy: a highest ultimate that is beyond all predication and specification (aparyāya-paramārtha ), in conformity with all Mādhyamika teachings, and an ultimate that can be inferred logically and specified meaningfully (paryāya-paramārtha ); this latter level was a bold innovation in the history of Mādhyamika thought. Of course, such a distinction was operative only within the realm of conventional thought. Again one must employ Bhāvaviveka's crucial adverbial codicil, paramārthataḥ, and follow him in claiming that such a distinction, like all distinctions, is ultimately unreal although conventionally useful.
Bhāvaviveka's two main philosophic contributions—his affirmation of a thesis on a conventional level and his reinterpretation of the two-truths doctrine—are evaluated diversely by contemporary scholars. Those unsympathetic to him see his work as an unhappy concession to the logical conventions of his day, a concession that dilutes the rigor of the Mādhyamika dialectic. Those with more sympathy see his contributions as a creative surge that rescued Buddhist religious philosophies from those dialectical negations that threatened the integrity of the Buddhist path itself.
Within the evolved Tibetan Buddhist tradition, Bhāvaviveka is especially known for two other contributions. His refutations of the rival Yogācāra school are considered to be among the clearest ever written. The fifth chapter of his Tarkajvālā, the "Yogācārattvaviniścaya," refutes both the existence of the absolute and the nonexistence of the conventional, both seminal Yogācāra positions.
He is also the forerunner of the literary style known as siddhānta (Tib., grub mthaʾ ), which became enormously popular within Tibetan scholarly circles. A siddhānta text devotes ordered chapters to analyzing the philosophic positions (siddhānta s) of rival schools, both Buddhist and Hindu. His Tarkajvālā contains systematic critiques of the positions held by the Hinayana and the Yogācāra, both Buddhist schools, and the Sāṃkhya, Vaisesika, Vedānta, and Mīmāṃsā schools of Hindu philosophy.
Bhāvaviveka was also a keen historian. His Nikāyab-hedavibhaṅgavyākhyāna remains one of the most important and reliable sources for the early history of the Buddhist order, and for information on the schisms within its ranks.
See Also
Buddhist Philosophy; Mādhyamika; Śūnyam and Śūnyata.
Bibliography
The most important philosophical works by Bhāvaviveka are his commentary on Nagarjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, the Prajñāpradīpa; his verse work, the Madhyama-kahṛdayakārikā, with the autocommentary the Tarkajvālā; his Madhyamārthasaṅgraha; and his Karatalaraṭna. All these works can be found in volumes 95 and 96 of The Tibetan Tripiṭaka, edited by D. T. Suzuki (Tokyo, 1962). Bhāvaviveka's work on the history of the Buddhist order, the Nikāyabhedavibhaṅgavyākhyāna, is included in volume 127.
Bhāvaviveka's biography can be found in Khetsun Sangpo's Rgya gar paṇ chen rnams kyi rnam thar ngo mtshar padmoʾi ʾdzum zhal gsar pa (Dharamsala, India, 1973). Perhaps the most definitive study of Bhāvaviveka is Malcolm David Eckel's "A Question of Nihilism: Bhāvaviveka's Response to the Fundamental Problems of Mādhyamika Philosophy" (Ph.D. diss., Harvard University, 1980). Shotaro Iida's Reason and Emptiness: A Study in Logic and Mysticism (Tokyo, 1980) studies Bhāvaviveka from the perspective of medieval Tibetan sources. Louis de La Vallée Poussin's essay "Bhāvaviveka," in volume 2 of Mélanges chinois et bouddhiques (Brussels, 1933), pp. 60–67, is the statement of classical Buddhology on the subject. Kajiyama Yuichi's "Bhāvaviveka and the Prāsaṅgika School," Nava-Nalanda-Mahavihara Research Publication 1 (n.d.): 289–331; my own "An Appraisal of the Svātantrika-Prasamgika Debates," Philosophy East and West 26 (1976): 253–267; Peter Della Santina's "The Division of the Madhyamika System into the Prāsaṅgika and Svātantrika Schools," Journal of Religious Studies 7 (1979): 40–49; and Ichimura Shohei's "A New Approach to the Intra-Mādhyamika Confrontation over the Svātantrika and Prāsaṅgika Methods of Refutation," Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 5 (1982): 41–52, exemplify contemporary scholarship. One important source was unavailable to this author: Donald Lopez's "The Svātantrika-Mādhyamika School of Mahāyāna Buddhism" (Ph.D. diss., University of Virginia, 1982).
Nathan Katz (1987)